The Completeness of Scientific Theories

On the Derivation of Empirical Indicators within a Theoretical Framework: The Case of Physical Geometry

Nonfiction, Science & Nature, Science, Physics, Mathematical Physics, Other Sciences, Philosophy & Social Aspects
Cover of the book The Completeness of Scientific Theories by Martin Carrier, Springer Netherlands
View on Amazon View on AbeBooks View on Kobo View on B.Depository View on eBay View on Walmart
Author: Martin Carrier ISBN: 9789401109109
Publisher: Springer Netherlands Publication: December 6, 2012
Imprint: Springer Language: English
Author: Martin Carrier
ISBN: 9789401109109
Publisher: Springer Netherlands
Publication: December 6, 2012
Imprint: Springer
Language: English

Earlier in this century, many philosophers of science (for example, Rudolf Carnap) drew a fairly sharp distinction between theory and observation, between theoretical terms like 'mass' and 'electron', and observation terms like 'measures three meters in length' and 'is _2° Celsius'. By simply looking at our instruments we can ascertain what numbers our measurements yield. Creatures like mass are different: we determine mass by calculation; we never directly observe a mass. Nor an electron: this term is introduced in order to explain what we observe. This (once standard) distinction between theory and observation was eventually found to be wanting. First, if the distinction holds, it is difficult to see what can characterize the relationship between theory :md observation. How can theoretical terms explain that which is itself in no way theorized? The second point leads out of the first: are not the instruments that provide us with observational material themselves creatures of theory? Is it really possible to have an observation language that is entirely barren of theory? The theory-Iadenness of observation languages is now an accept­ ed feature of the logic of science. Many regard such dependence of observation on theory as a virtue. If our instruments of observation do not derive their meaning from theories, whence comes that meaning? Surely - in science - we have nothing else but theories to tell us what to try to observe.

View on Amazon View on AbeBooks View on Kobo View on B.Depository View on eBay View on Walmart

Earlier in this century, many philosophers of science (for example, Rudolf Carnap) drew a fairly sharp distinction between theory and observation, between theoretical terms like 'mass' and 'electron', and observation terms like 'measures three meters in length' and 'is _2° Celsius'. By simply looking at our instruments we can ascertain what numbers our measurements yield. Creatures like mass are different: we determine mass by calculation; we never directly observe a mass. Nor an electron: this term is introduced in order to explain what we observe. This (once standard) distinction between theory and observation was eventually found to be wanting. First, if the distinction holds, it is difficult to see what can characterize the relationship between theory :md observation. How can theoretical terms explain that which is itself in no way theorized? The second point leads out of the first: are not the instruments that provide us with observational material themselves creatures of theory? Is it really possible to have an observation language that is entirely barren of theory? The theory-Iadenness of observation languages is now an accept­ ed feature of the logic of science. Many regard such dependence of observation on theory as a virtue. If our instruments of observation do not derive their meaning from theories, whence comes that meaning? Surely - in science - we have nothing else but theories to tell us what to try to observe.

More books from Springer Netherlands

Cover of the book Ethics at Work by Martin Carrier
Cover of the book Climate Change and United States Forests by Martin Carrier
Cover of the book Social Decision Methodology for Technological Projects by Martin Carrier
Cover of the book The Idea of Order by Martin Carrier
Cover of the book Revolution, Idealism and Human Freedom: Schelling Hölderlin and Hegel and the Crisis of Early German Idealism by Martin Carrier
Cover of the book Physics at Seventeenth and Eighteenth-Century Leiden: Philosophy and the New Science in the University by Martin Carrier
Cover of the book Local Environmental Change and Society in Africa by Martin Carrier
Cover of the book Liberty in Hume’s History of England by Martin Carrier
Cover of the book Edible Medicinal And Non Medicinal Plants by Martin Carrier
Cover of the book Links Between Beliefs and Cognitive Flexibility by Martin Carrier
Cover of the book Advanced Imaging in Coronary Artery Disease by Martin Carrier
Cover of the book Immunological Aspects of Rheumatology by Martin Carrier
Cover of the book Biochemical Genetics by Martin Carrier
Cover of the book How is Society Possible? by Martin Carrier
Cover of the book Henry Home, Lord Kames and the Scottish Enlightenment by Martin Carrier
We use our own "cookies" and third party cookies to improve services and to see statistical information. By using this website, you agree to our Privacy Policy